Concept

Admissible rule

Summary
In logic, a rule of inference is admissible in a formal system if the set of theorems of the system does not change when that rule is added to the existing rules of the system. In other words, every formula that can be derived using that rule is already derivable without that rule, so, in a sense, it is redundant. The concept of an admissible rule was introduced by Paul Lorenzen (1955). Admissibility has been systematically studied only in the case of structural (i.e. substitution-closed) rules in propositional non-classical logics, which we will describe next. Let a set of basic propositional connectives be fixed (for instance, in the case of superintuitionistic logics, or in the case of monomodal logics). Well-formed formulas are built freely using these connectives from a countably infinite set of propositional variables p0, p1, .... A substitution σ is a function from formulas to formulas that commutes with applications of the connectives, i.e., for every connective f, and formulas A1, ... , An. (We may also apply substitutions to sets Γ of formulas, making σΓ = {σA: A ∈ Γ}.) A Tarski-style consequence relation is a relation between sets of formulas, and formulas, such that for all formulas A, B, and sets of formulas Γ, Δ. A consequence relation such that for all substitutions σ is called structural. (Note that the term "structural" as used here and below is unrelated to the notion of structural rules in sequent calculi.) A structural consequence relation is called a propositional logic. A formula A is a theorem of a logic if . For example, we identify a superintuitionistic logic L with its standard consequence relation generated by modus ponens and axioms, and we identify a normal modal logic with its global consequence relation generated by modus ponens, necessitation, and (as axioms) the theorems of the logic. A structural inference rule (or just rule for short) is given by a pair (Γ, B), usually written as where Γ = {A1, ... , An} is a finite set of formulas, and B is a formula. An instance of the rule is for a substitution σ.
About this result
This page is automatically generated and may contain information that is not correct, complete, up-to-date, or relevant to your search query. The same applies to every other page on this website. Please make sure to verify the information with EPFL's official sources.